StartGroepenDiscussieMeerTijdgeest
Doorzoek de site
Onze site gebruikt cookies om diensten te leveren, prestaties te verbeteren, voor analyse en (indien je niet ingelogd bent) voor advertenties. Door LibraryThing te gebruiken erken je dat je onze Servicevoorwaarden en Privacybeleid gelezen en begrepen hebt. Je gebruik van de site en diensten is onderhevig aan dit beleid en deze voorwaarden.

Resultaten uit Google Boeken

Klik op een omslag om naar Google Boeken te gaan.

Bezig met laden...

The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought (1957)

door Thomas S. Kuhn

Andere auteurs: Zie de sectie andere auteurs.

LedenBesprekingenPopulariteitGemiddelde beoordelingAanhalingen
8611125,072 (4.23)14
"The author brings to a common focus the considered approach of the historian, the technical understanding of the scientist and the skill and experience of an able teacher. No careful reader of this well-wrought volume can fail to appreciate the nicely balanced interplay of these elements in the full explication of one of the major turning points in the evolution of scientific thought. For those concerned with the teaching of the history of science, this discussion of the issues involved in the Copernican revolution will prove to be indispensable, a superb analysis of the anatomy of revolution. Those drawn to the question of meaning which the historian of science can give to the evolution of ideas will find this book equally valuable, a paradigm of synthesis and interpretation." [Isis]… (meer)
Bezig met laden...

Meld je aan bij LibraryThing om erachter te komen of je dit boek goed zult vinden.

Op dit moment geen Discussie gesprekken over dit boek.

» Zie ook 14 vermeldingen

Engels (8)  Catalaans (1)  Spaans (1)  Alle talen (10)
1-5 van 10 worden getoond (volgende | toon alle)
A solid addition to the literature of science history and intellectual history. Kuhn sets out the interesting ways by which the astronomical system of Copurnicus generated the revolution named for him.

The book is interesting in detail and breadth and is fairly easily reading not compromised by philosophical obfuscation. I do not sense that Kuhn is out of his depth at any point. He exaggerates his viewpoint only somewhat. I believe it will interest any non-scientist as well as any scientist not already familiar both with the historical details presented and with their significance in a historical view reaching back to Aristotle and forward to Newton. There are some simple diagrams which require attention, but few of them need to be studied so long as the reader understands from the text their meaning. Similarly, no math is needed. Any layman who believes science is mostly a collection of facts must read this in order to have a sense of a type of process that science is truly about.

Importantly, the Copernican (sun-centered) astronomy, says Kuhn, resulted in no obvious overall simplification over the Ptolemaic system (with epicycles, which are moving circles within orbits and had been adopted along with other unrealities in order to describe the apparent motions of the heavens around the earth). Copernicus did not, for example, eliminate most of the epicycles. While he did simplify some matters, he rendered others more complicated. For example, in order to make his system correspond to observation, he had to add some (unreal) motion not present in Ptolemy. The primary task for Copernicus was to prove mathematically that his system was observationally consistent with Ptolemy, since the received Ptolemaic system was as accurate as current observations allowed and was, as shown by Kuhn, accurate generally to a degree which the Copernican description did not exceed. The superiority his new system was not at all clear.

(It was a problem with the calendar that likely motivated Copernicus to look for a better system. Ironically, It was a church authority who asked him whether he could resolve the problem. Furthermore, his formulation did not finally result in a solution to it.)

Why and how then did the Copernican revolution result? While its influence tends to be considered in terms of its theological and philosophical implications, the answer to the question lies elsewhere, since this was fundamentally a scientific revolution.

This question presents to the historian a challenge which Kuhn masters in this book. He shows that some of the answer lies in the historical significance of modest ad hoc evolutionary accretions made to Ptolemaic astronomy before Copernicus. (More, below.)

Much else lies in the incremental recognition by post-Copernican astronomers of various advantages of this system, quite small advantages early on. These advantages could not be seen until later (initially in large part because of improvements made in the accuracy of astronomical observations after he died). They accumulated and supported one another, along with successive theoretical modifications over time, to the extent that his system largely has been replaced. Today it can as easily be seen as more nearly Ptolemaic than as Newtonian or Einsteinian.

But similar as the views of Ptolemy and Copernicus were, the revolution would not have arisen from a Ptolemaic view, because the evolution of that view would have continued the same way it always had since the time of Ptolemy, by adding additional epicycles and other unrealities whenever necessary in order to fit new data, as indeed Ptolemy had done to the Aristotelian cosmology in order to arrive at his own. Copernicus proved that an abrupt disruption in this kind of evolutionary procession, by moving the center of the universe from earth to sun rather than adding more epicycles, could result in an equally acceptable astronomy. The change in the process itself, this fundamental difference in procedure only, became a leap more important than any immedate astronomical consequences of the new theory.

But this change could not be appreciated at first. In the larger scientific community of the decades after his death, even the sun-centered nature of the theory was largely ignored, as it contradicted the senses, tradition and religious authority. It became preferentially taught because it clearly set out in one elegant treatise the means of making mathematical calculations describing celestial observations. (The Ptolemaic formulation had passed through the centuries in often second-hand accounts and varying translations and re-translations, additions and other editing.) Only as increasingly accurate astronomical data more strongly matched the Copernican universe did the teaching of his system to other scientists become securely established.

Only later as the remaining Ptolemaic elements fell away due to more sophisticated data collection and more ingenious mathematical treatment did the best mathematicians begin to appreciate more fully the scientific value of the new and evolving system. Since the Copernican leap in process had already been proved by him to lead to a defensible scientific result, and the conception was proving even more useful over time, mathematicians were now at liberty to attempt further procedural leaps of imagination in search of better answers. Importantly, they could find increasingly general formulations (like universal gravity) in order to explain and simplify elegantly a greater number of observations, rather than further complicate matters as would result by piling on more epicycles. The revolution is named for Copernicus because he afforded this new liberty of scientific imagination which eventually proved so fruitful.

Only after the newer formulations proved their power could the wider scientific community and then the educated public begin fully to accept the revolution and attempt reasonably to assess what broader implications might be implied by this revolutionary theory.

( )
  KENNERLYDAN | Jul 11, 2021 |
FG-6
  Murtra | Oct 10, 2020 |
LA REVOLUCIÓN COPERNICANA

La presente obra muestra que la revolución copernicana no ha
perdido su valor en la actualidad.

Por tratarse de un acontecimiento en el desarrollo de la actividad
intelectual, en el que se pone de manifiesto que la solución de
un problema científico puede producir un cambio radical en las
actitudes y formas de pensamiento de la humanidad, el análisis
de los procesos intelectuales que constituyen la base de dicha
revolución nos permite alcanzar una nueva perspectiva en nuestra
era científica, para valorar de un modo más inteligente nuestras
propias creencias los fundamentos de nuestra metodología y,
en general, todo lo que afecta a la creatividad humana.

Thomas S. Kuhn. cuya obra “La estructura de las revoluciones científicas”
ha marcado un hito de gran trascendencia en la filosofía de la
ciencia actual, expone en su revolución copernicana el contenido y
significado de este hecho, no sólo como un episodio interno de la
astronomía, sino como un punto de partida de la crisis del
pensamiento occidental y de la transformación del concepto del
hombre y de su relación con el universo.
  FundacionRosacruz | May 29, 2018 |
Apart from the scientific import of the Copernican Revolution, Kuhn's book plays an illustrative role in the still needed polemic against Christian fundamentalism. It provides (at least hints at) parallels between the fundamentalist arguments against evolution (and other science influenced practices) and the old biblical arguments against Copernicus. ( )
  Darrol | Oct 10, 2010 |
(posted on my blog: davenichols.net)

Historian of science Thomas Kuhn served up this foundational and mathematical history of the Copernican Revolution, that amazing period of time which saw man's idea of a geocentric universe replaced with a more accurate heliocentric one. Copernicus himself delivered the foundational work, De revolutionibus orbium coelestium libri six ("Six Books on the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres"), which forever influenced the course of science's understanding of planetary motion.

Kuhn's history covers the pre-Renaissance groundwork laid down from ancient times, especially in works by Aristole and Ptolemy, and moves the story through the problems associated with these accepted models. Copernicus himself is largely ignored until much later in the book as Kuhn makes sure the reader understands just why Copernicus felt the need to break from tradition and put forth an alternative model.

Once De revolutionibus is published and spreads, Kuhn follows the story on through the later work of Brahe, Kepler, and Galileo, as well as explaining just why this Revolution was such a pronounced one in hindsight.

Kuhn's writing is very exact, and he can be a bit meticulous with some of the geometry. I loved this, but I recognize that some popular history of science readers might find this a bit too technical. Anyway, Kuhn is an excellent historian and presents a well-written and concise account of one of the most important periods in the history of science. Four stars. ( )
2 stem IslandDave | Sep 15, 2009 |
1-5 van 10 worden getoond (volgende | toon alle)
geen besprekingen | voeg een bespreking toe

» Andere auteurs toevoegen (1 mogelijk)

AuteursnaamRolType auteurWerk?Status
Thomas S. Kuhnprimaire auteuralle editiesberekend
Conant, James B.VoorwoordSecundaire auteursommige editiesbevestigd
Je moet ingelogd zijn om Algemene Kennis te mogen bewerken.
Voor meer hulp zie de helppagina Algemene Kennis .
Gangbare titel
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Oorspronkelijke titel
Alternatieve titels
Oorspronkelijk jaar van uitgave
Mensen/Personages
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Belangrijke plaatsen
Belangrijke gebeurtenissen
Verwante films
Motto
Opdracht
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
To L.K. Nash
For a vehement collaboration
Eerste woorden
Citaten
Laatste woorden
Ontwarringsbericht
Uitgevers redacteuren
Auteur van flaptekst/aanprijzing
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Oorspronkelijke taal
Informatie uit de Spaanse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Gangbare DDC/MDS
Canonieke LCC
"The author brings to a common focus the considered approach of the historian, the technical understanding of the scientist and the skill and experience of an able teacher. No careful reader of this well-wrought volume can fail to appreciate the nicely balanced interplay of these elements in the full explication of one of the major turning points in the evolution of scientific thought. For those concerned with the teaching of the history of science, this discussion of the issues involved in the Copernican revolution will prove to be indispensable, a superb analysis of the anatomy of revolution. Those drawn to the question of meaning which the historian of science can give to the evolution of ideas will find this book equally valuable, a paradigm of synthesis and interpretation." [Isis]

Geen bibliotheekbeschrijvingen gevonden.

Boekbeschrijving
Haiku samenvatting

Actuele discussies

Geen

Populaire omslagen

Snelkoppelingen

Waardering

Gemiddelde: (4.23)
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5 1
3 6
3.5 2
4 22
4.5 3
5 19

Ben jij dit?

Word een LibraryThing Auteur.

 

Over | Contact | LibraryThing.com | Privacy/Voorwaarden | Help/Veelgestelde vragen | Blog | Winkel | APIs | TinyCat | Nagelaten Bibliotheken | Vroege Recensenten | Algemene kennis | 204,711,791 boeken! | Bovenbalk: Altijd zichtbaar