StartGroepenDiscussieMeerTijdgeest
Doorzoek de site
Onze site gebruikt cookies om diensten te leveren, prestaties te verbeteren, voor analyse en (indien je niet ingelogd bent) voor advertenties. Door LibraryThing te gebruiken erken je dat je onze Servicevoorwaarden en Privacybeleid gelezen en begrepen hebt. Je gebruik van de site en diensten is onderhevig aan dit beleid en deze voorwaarden.

Resultaten uit Google Boeken

Klik op een omslag om naar Google Boeken te gaan.

Bezig met laden...

De menselijke kennis haar omvang en beperkingen (1948)

door Bertrand Russell

Andere auteurs: Zie de sectie andere auteurs.

LedenBesprekingenPopulariteitGemiddelde beoordelingAanhalingen
405362,285 (3.94)2
How do we know what we "know"? How did we -as individuals and as a society - come to accept certain knowledge as fact? In Human Knowledge, Bertrand Russell questions the reliability of our assumptions on knowledge. This brilliant and controversial work investigates the relationship between 'individual' and 'scientific' knowledge. First published in 1948, this provocative work contributed significantly to an explosive intellectual discourse that continues to this day.… (meer)
Bezig met laden...

Meld je aan bij LibraryThing om erachter te komen of je dit boek goed zult vinden.

Op dit moment geen Discussie gesprekken over dit boek.

» Zie ook 2 vermeldingen

Engels (2)  Catalaans (1)  Alle talen (3)
Toon 3 van 3
This is a book written for the general reader, with the aim of presenting a system that allows us to come by something that we can claim as being knowledge; he tries to deal with the problem of induction. The work appears to be motivated by a desire to philosophically justify the common sense beliefs and behaviour of scientists, and to provide context the book opens with a brief summary of the important things that we know in each of the different fields of science ( circa 1950).
The book is over 500 pages, and there are lengthy discussions on all the relevant areas. These are broken down as far as possible into small chapters, which makes this book more readable than it might otherwise have been. Some of the most important topics which make up the argument presented here are: knowledge, causality, inference, language, observation, other minds, structure, probability, and logic. Probability is probably what is relied on most in escaping the induction problem itself, and this is what in fact nearly all scientists do use to support their hypotheses, after they have collected their empirical data. In the section on probability he dissects several systems of probability, including one of Keynes', then appears to come to some vague conclusion that the use of statistical systems can be justified practically by their successful performance in predicting future phenomena (and this also can be measured statistically). So, empiricism is justified because it works, which is essentially what other books on this problem have decided, though they often reach this from slightly different angles. The section on probability is not light reading, with plenty of formulas, so if the reader is not a keen mathematician, some parts will either be hard work or worth passing over.
It might be worthwhile to compare this book to "The Problem of Knowledge" by A J Ayer, who was a contemporary of Russell who sought to deal with the same problem. Russell's book is more difficult to read (though his style is good and dry wit amusing), and is twice as long, because it deals more thoroughly with several relevant peripheral issues and includes some that Ayer does not. Ayer's book doesn't deal with the practicalities of science, (with which it could be argued that a philosopher needn't concern himself), however Russell rolls his sleeves up and tackles them quite well. Reading between the lines in Ayer, I think he and Russell both share several sentiments on the subject. Neither embrace scepticism (though acknowledging the sceptics point), and both are first class logicians who want to justify a common sense approach to science. Russell's work is the more impressive, due to its its comprehensive scope and greater completeness as a system, but Ayer's work has a greater elegance due in part to its avoidance of clunky topics such as probability which are not traditionally favoured by philosophers. So, anyone interested in understanding the problem would do well to read both books, but Russell's, despite arguably possessing more authority, is less easily approached and requires more effort in parts to digest. ( )
2 stem P_S_Patrick | Dec 31, 2011 |
FG-5
  Murtra | Oct 29, 2020 |
Russell, at his analytical best, explores what can be known and what constitutes knowledge itself. ( )
  Len_hart | Dec 2, 2007 |
Toon 3 van 3
geen besprekingen | voeg een bespreking toe

» Andere auteurs toevoegen (6 mogelijk)

AuteursnaamRolType auteurWerk?Status
Bertrand Russellprimaire auteuralle editiesberekend
Slater, John G.IntroductieSecundaire auteursommige editiesbevestigd

Onderdeel van de uitgeversreeks(en)

Je moet ingelogd zijn om Algemene Kennis te mogen bewerken.
Voor meer hulp zie de helppagina Algemene Kennis .
Gangbare titel
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Oorspronkelijke titel
Alternatieve titels
Oorspronkelijk jaar van uitgave
Mensen/Personages
Belangrijke plaatsen
Belangrijke gebeurtenissen
Verwante films
Motto
Opdracht
Eerste woorden
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Introduction -- The central purpose of this book is to examine the relation between individual experience and the general body of scientific knowledge. It is taken for granted that scientific knowledge, in its broad outlines, is to be accepted. Skepticism, while logically impeccable, is psychologically impossible, and there is an element of frivolous insincerity in any philosophy which pretends to accept it. Moreover, if skepticism is to be theoretically defensible, it must reject all inference from what is experienced; a partial skepticism, such as the denial of physical events experienced by no one, or a solipsism which allows events in my future or in my unremembered past, has no logical justification, since it must admit principles of inference which lead to beliefs that it rejects.
Citaten
Laatste woorden
Informatie afkomstig uit de Engelse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
(Klik om weer te geven. Waarschuwing: kan de inhoud verklappen.)
Ontwarringsbericht
Uitgevers redacteuren
Auteur van flaptekst/aanprijzing
Oorspronkelijke taal
Informatie uit de Spaanse Algemene Kennis. Bewerk om naar jouw taal over te brengen.
Gangbare DDC/MDS
Canonieke LCC

Verwijzingen naar dit werk in externe bronnen.

Wikipedia in het Engels (1)

How do we know what we "know"? How did we -as individuals and as a society - come to accept certain knowledge as fact? In Human Knowledge, Bertrand Russell questions the reliability of our assumptions on knowledge. This brilliant and controversial work investigates the relationship between 'individual' and 'scientific' knowledge. First published in 1948, this provocative work contributed significantly to an explosive intellectual discourse that continues to this day.

Geen bibliotheekbeschrijvingen gevonden.

Boekbeschrijving
Haiku samenvatting

Actuele discussies

Geen

Populaire omslagen

Snelkoppelingen

Waardering

Gemiddelde: (3.94)
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5
3 4
3.5 2
4 7
4.5
5 4

Ben jij dit?

Word een LibraryThing Auteur.

 

Over | Contact | LibraryThing.com | Privacy/Voorwaarden | Help/Veelgestelde vragen | Blog | Winkel | APIs | TinyCat | Nagelaten Bibliotheken | Vroege Recensenten | Algemene kennis | 204,459,324 boeken! | Bovenbalk: Altijd zichtbaar